Quotes & Sayings


We, and creation itself, actualize the possibilities of the God who sustains the world, towards becoming in the world in a fuller, more deeper way. - R.E. Slater

There is urgency in coming to see the world as a web of interrelated processes of which we are integral parts, so that all of our choices and actions have [consequential effects upon] the world around us. - Process Metaphysician Alfred North Whitehead

Kurt Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem says (i) all closed systems are unprovable within themselves and, that (ii) all open systems are rightly understood as incomplete. - R.E. Slater

The most true thing about you is what God has said to you in Christ, "You are My Beloved." - Tripp Fuller

The God among us is the God who refuses to be God without us, so great is God's Love. - Tripp Fuller

According to some Christian outlooks we were made for another world. Perhaps, rather, we were made for this world to recreate, reclaim, redeem, and renew unto God's future aspiration by the power of His Spirit. - R.E. Slater

Our eschatological ethos is to love. To stand with those who are oppressed. To stand against those who are oppressing. It is that simple. Love is our only calling and Christian Hope. - R.E. Slater

Secularization theory has been massively falsified. We don't live in an age of secularity. We live in an age of explosive, pervasive religiosity... an age of religious pluralism. - Peter L. Berger

Exploring the edge of life and faith in a post-everything world. - Todd Littleton

I don't need another reason to believe, your love is all around for me to see. – Anon

Thou art our need; and in giving us more of thyself thou givest us all. - Khalil Gibran, Prayer XXIII

Be careful what you pretend to be. You become what you pretend to be. - Kurt Vonnegut

Religious beliefs, far from being primary, are often shaped and adjusted by our social goals. - Jim Forest

We become who we are by what we believe and can justify. - R.E. Slater

People, even more than things, need to be restored, renewed, revived, reclaimed, and redeemed; never throw out anyone. – Anon

Certainly, God's love has made fools of us all. - R.E. Slater

An apocalyptic Christian faith doesn't wait for Jesus to come, but for Jesus to become in our midst. - R.E. Slater

Christian belief in God begins with the cross and resurrection of Jesus, not with rational apologetics. - Eberhard Jüngel, Jürgen Moltmann

Our knowledge of God is through the 'I-Thou' encounter, not in finding God at the end of a syllogism or argument. There is a grave danger in any Christian treatment of God as an object. The God of Jesus Christ and Scripture is irreducibly subject and never made as an object, a force, a power, or a principle that can be manipulated. - Emil Brunner

“Ehyeh Asher Ehyeh” means "I will be that who I have yet to become." - God (Ex 3.14) or, conversely, “I AM who I AM Becoming.”

Our job is to love others without stopping to inquire whether or not they are worthy. - Thomas Merton

The church is God's world-changing social experiment of bringing unlikes and differents to the Eucharist/Communion table to share life with one another as a new kind of family. When this happens, we show to the world what love, justice, peace, reconciliation, and life together is designed by God to be. The church is God's show-and-tell for the world to see how God wants us to live as a blended, global, polypluralistic family united with one will, by one Lord, and baptized by one Spirit. – Anon

The cross that is planted at the heart of the history of the world cannot be uprooted. - Jacques Ellul

The Unity in whose loving presence the universe unfolds is inside each person as a call to welcome the stranger, protect animals and the earth, respect the dignity of each person, think new thoughts, and help bring about ecological civilizations. - John Cobb & Farhan A. Shah

If you board the wrong train it is of no use running along the corridors of the train in the other direction. - Dietrich Bonhoeffer

God's justice is restorative rather than punitive; His discipline is merciful rather than punishing; His power is made perfect in weakness; and His grace is sufficient for all. – Anon

Our little [biblical] systems have their day; they have their day and cease to be. They are but broken lights of Thee, and Thou, O God art more than they. - Alfred Lord Tennyson

We can’t control God; God is uncontrollable. God can’t control us; God’s love is uncontrolling! - Thomas Jay Oord

Life in perspective but always in process... as we are relational beings in process to one another, so life events are in process in relation to each event... as God is to Self, is to world, is to us... like Father, like sons and daughters, like events... life in process yet always in perspective. - R.E. Slater

To promote societal transition to sustainable ways of living and a global society founded on a shared ethical framework which includes respect and care for the community of life, ecological integrity, universal human rights, respect for diversity, economic justice, democracy, and a culture of peace. - The Earth Charter Mission Statement

Christian humanism is the belief that human freedom, individual conscience, and unencumbered rational inquiry are compatible with the practice of Christianity or even intrinsic in its doctrine. It represents a philosophical union of Christian faith and classical humanist principles. - Scott Postma

It is never wise to have a self-appointed religious institution determine a nation's moral code. The opportunities for moral compromise and failure are high; the moral codes and creeds assuredly racist, discriminatory, or subjectively and religiously defined; and the pronouncement of inhumanitarian political objectives quite predictable. - R.E. Slater

God's love must both center and define the Christian faith and all religious or human faiths seeking human and ecological balance in worlds of subtraction, harm, tragedy, and evil. - R.E. Slater

In Whitehead’s process ontology, we can think of the experiential ground of reality as an eternal pulse whereby what is objectively public in one moment becomes subjectively prehended in the next, and whereby the subject that emerges from its feelings then perishes into public expression as an object (or “superject”) aiming for novelty. There is a rhythm of Being between object and subject, not an ontological division. This rhythm powers the creative growth of the universe from one occasion of experience to the next. This is the Whiteheadian mantra: “The many become one and are increased by one.” - Matthew Segall

Without Love there is no Truth. And True Truth is always Loving. There is no dichotomy between these terms but only seamless integration. This is the premier centering focus of a Processual Theology of Love. - R.E. Slater

-----

Note: Generally I do not respond to commentary. I may read the comments but wish to reserve my time to write (or write from the comments I read). Instead, I'd like to see our community help one another and in the helping encourage and exhort each of us towards Christian love in Christ Jesus our Lord and Savior. - re slater

Saturday, June 8, 2024

Whitehead's Process Metaphysics as a New Link Between Science and Metaphysics


WHITEHEAD PROCESS METAPHYSICS AS A
NEW LINK BETWEEN SIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

by Nelson Shang
THE UNIVERSITY OF BAMENDA
February 2020

All content was uploaded by Nelson Shang on 13 March 2021. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) Volume 4 Issue 2, February 2020 Available Online: www.ijtsrd.com e-ISSN: 2456 – 6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 242

~ ~  Unedited ABSTRACT found further below  ~ ~












UNEDITED ABSTRACT

Against the separation of metaphysics and science (advocated for by Plato and his followers); and against the rejection of metaphysics in favour of science (the Logical Positivists), this work argues that ‘a new link’ between metaphysics and science is all the more necessary for man to better understand nature. This is precisely what Whitehead’s process metaphysics purports to do. But why is ‘a new link’ necessary? It is necessary because Aristotle (and his followers) already established a link (‘an old link’) by making metaphysics the foundation of all the sciences. Yet, Aristotelian metaphysics is a substance-based metaphysics while Whitehead’s metaphysics takes process and especially the category of relation seriously. Whitehead’s Process metaphysics prioritizes process over permanence, becoming over being, relation over substance. Why does Whitehead have such preference for process metaphysics over classical metaphysics? The answer, as shall be shown in this paper, lies in science with the demise of Newtonian science and the rise of Einsteinian science based on the theory of relativity. In an era when the concept of depassement de la metaphysique has become such a dominant feature of modern and postmodern thought, it is therefore our point of interest to find out why Whitehead (who situates himself within this period) takes up metaphysics as the foundation of his philosophizing: Why does Whitehead embark on reconciling science and metaphysics when all his contemporaries are dissociating themselves from the former? These questions will be the main concern of my research in this paper. Key words: Process Metaphysics, actual entity, eternal objects,Creativity, Concrescence, Prehension How to cite this paper: Nelson Shang "Whitehead’s Process Metaphysics as a New Link between Science and Metaphysics" Published in International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (ijtsrd), ISSN: 2456- 6470, Volume-4 | Issue-2, February 2020, pp.242-250, URL: www.ijtsrd.com/papers/ijtsrd29982.pdf Copyright © 2019 by author(s) and International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development Journal. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY 4.0) (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by /4.0) I. The scientific ‘Sources’ of Process metaphysics The proper understanding of a philosopher’s thought requires a clear appreciation of the problems and issues with which he was concerned, and of the context in which they presented themselves to him. This certainly is a most important requirement for understanding the metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead. Whitehead’s background was an unusual one for a speculative metaphysician. He was educated as a mathematician and a physicist and wrote much on physics and its philosophy. He began his writing in process and metaphysics only when he joined HarvardUniversity at the age of 63. Viewed chronologically, it is evident that Whitehead’s earliest philosophical preoccupation was with the philosophical problems of modern science which had become acute with the new developments that had taken place at the beginning of the 20th century. His writings at this time were devoted exclusively to these problems.1 These works include: The Organization of Thought 1917, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural knowledge 1919, and The Concept of Nature1920. It is therefore indubitable that in his 1LECLERC I., Whitehead’s Metaphysics: An Introductory Exposition (London, 1958) online version at http://www.questia.com/readers/action/open/10305739# 1 (page consulted on the 8th of August 2011). later writings his concern with the problems of modern science and its philosophy played a significant part. Here we have among others Science and the Modern World 1925 and Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, 1929. Whitehead’s devotion to metaphysics came later. Javier Monserrat explains that when Whitehead began with metaphysics, he already had an image of the world in his mind. The critical factor that caused him to crossover into metaphysics is the idea that science had turned traditional metaphysics head over heels and that it was necessary to create a new metaphysics that’s congruent with it. He justified this assertion with Whitehead’s view that science demands a transformation of the world in order to make it “modern”: it is science that makes the world modern requiring both a metaphysics and religion that are “modern”.2 This explains why Whitehead began the preface to his Science and the Modern World by noting that the human intuitions of science, aesthetics, ethics, and religion each make a positive contribution to the worldview of a community. In each historical period, any one or combination of these intuitions may receive emphasis and 2MONSERRAT J.,Alfred n. Whitehead on Process Philosophy and Theology: Cosmos and Kenosis of Divinityin Pensamiento, vol. 64 (2008), num. 242 p. 824. IJTSRD29982 International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 243 thus influence the dominant worldview of its people. It is a peculiar characteristic of the last three (now four) centuries that scientific pursuits have come to dominate the worldview of Western minds. For this reason, Whitehead seeks to establish a comprehensive cosmology—understood here in the sense of a systematic descriptive theory of the world—that does justice to all of the human intuitions and not only the scientific ones.3 Hence, looking at the patent dissolution of the comfortable scheme of scientific materialism which has dominated the last three centuries, Whitehead: Endeavoured to outline an alternative ontological doctrine, which shall be wide enough to include what is fundamental both for science and for its critics. In this alternative scheme, the notion of material, as fundamental, has been replaced by that of organic synthesis. But the approach has always been from the consideration of the actual intricacies of scientific thought, and of the peculiar perplexities which it suggests.4 InScience and the Modern World Whitehead presents a scientific image of the world that influenced his whole philosophy. Between 1924 and 1925, Heisenberg and Schrödinger developed “Matrix Mechanics” and “Wave Mechanics” respectively. These had a great influence on Whitehead as evidenced in his Science and the Modern World and especially in Process and Reality. Monserrat explains that the demise of classical atomism brought on by the dematerialization of physical matter through the rise of the quantum theory brought much aid and comfort to a processoriented metaphysics. Twentieth century physics has thus turned the tables on classical atomism. Instead of very small things (atoms) combining to produce standard processes (windstorms and such) modern physics envisions very small processes (quantum phenomena) combining to produce standard things (ordinary macro-objects) as a result of their modus operandi.Therefore, for Whitehead, it was obvious that the 20th century described a world in “flux” with unstable events that interacted with each other by way of physical prehensions in order to construct real entities in the same way that societies of organised events dynamically transformed a continuous process.5 Furthermore, the 19th century introduced a radically novel perspective to the understanding of the world: the evolutionary point of view. In this regard, J. Monserrat again says: Classical metaphysics and philosophy responded to the world in a “constructed” state; evolution, in turn, imposed the view of a dynamic world continually in process. To understand the general properties of this new world described by science, the “first philosophy”: graecoscholastic or Cartesian-mechanistic metaphysics was not enough. Many thinkers noticed this trend. Because of this, the philosophy of the end of the 19th and beginning of the 20th centuries was full of attempts to create a new metaphysics; the metaphysics of a new image of the world born of science.6 3WHITEHEAD, A. N., Science and the Modern World, p. viii. 4Ibid., p. 157. 5Cf., MONSERRAT J., Alfred N. Whitehead on Process Philosophy and theology: Cosmos and Kenosis of Divinity inPensamiento, vol. 64 (2008), num. 242 p. 824. 6Ibidem. One of the trends of this new philosophy was made up of vitalism. In effect, the world up until this point was understood from the point of a static, dualist graecoscholastic philosophy or from the scientific paradigm of the machine (Cartesian mechanism). It was imperative to build an understanding of the world from an organic paradigm7 of life in evolution. In this light, Hustwit maintains: For not only is evolution a process that makes philosophers and philosophy possible, but it provides a clear model for how processual novelty and innovation comes into operation in nature's self-engendering and self-perpetuating scheme of things. Evolution, be it of organism or of mind, of subatomic matter or of the cosmos as a whole, reflects the pervasive role of process which philosophers of this school see as central both to the nature of our world and to the terms in which it must be understood.8 For Monserrat, “this gestating vitalism was present throughout Europe, mainly in France and Germany but was also an essential ingredient of the North American pragmatism.”9 Whitehead was greatly influenced by these pragmatists and by H. Bergson. Before Whitehead came into philosophy Bergson had published his great works and had international fame. In Science and the Modern World Whitehead frequently makes mentions of Bergsonian metaphysics. First of all, Whitehead saw the universe as engaged in a truly creative advance, an advance leading to higher forms of value, importance and richness. It is essential to the universe that it comes from a definite past and moves ahead, sometimes after failures and regressions, to higher achievements. The whole world is dynamic and has a thrust for higher values.10 Also, on the cultural level, mankind is ever striving for the realization of some ideal, proper to each age, to be achieved within a certain period of time. The ideal is never realized in its perfection, but it is under the attraction of the ideal that men, as individuals and as members of a society, have the incentive to move ahead to the best of their ability.11 The last and most important reason comes from the science. The science of Whitehead’s day gave evidence of a progressive evolution at work that shows that nature, as we know it today, has passed through higher and higher stages from inorganic matter to organic matter. With the new scientific discoveries on the early 20th centuries and especially with the quantum theory, the Newtonian science that had led to scientific materialism was no longer viable to explain the nature of the universe. The universe must be in motion, must be made up of events – energy like processes – and not static atoms. Whitehead, in his most creative years, followed the deliberation of quantum mechanics according to which physical reality consisted of corpuscular matter12 7Hence Henri Bergson’s Elan Vital, Whitehead’s Philosophy of Organism 8Cf., J. R. HUSTWIT,Process Philosophy inStandford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, online version athttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/process-philosophy/. 9MONSERRAT J.,Alfred N. Whitehead on Process Philosophy and theology, p. 825. 10A. N. WHITEHEAD,Modes of Thought, New York: Macmillan, 1938, pp. 16, 206-208. 11Ibid.,pp. 164-165. 12‘Corpuscles’ are small units of matter of various shapes and with various physical properties that interact with one International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 244 that at the same time was a wave. He found in microphysical events, such as electrons in their quantum orbit, that Physics at the beginning of the 20th Century described a world in “flux.” The 19th Century evolutionary theories equally imposed on him the view of a dynamic world continually in process.13 Looking at the world from these three perspectives, Whitehead concluded that the fundamental fact of our experience is process. This does not mean sheer activity operating at random. Whitehead was constantly bothered by the question on why there should be process. Why should things act at all? Why should the world, on the broad cultural level and on the narrower scientific level, be continually striving for higher achievement? Why should things act at all?14 These and others are the questions that Whitehead felt that science had left unanswered but that these demanded a deeper insight into the “metaphysical nature of things.”15 Whitehead, therefore, developed his philosophy with the hope that it might illuminate “the ultimate aim infused into the process of nature.”16 Even though the term process philosophy (metaphysics) is primarily associated with the work of Whitehead, process philosophy is a long-standing philosophical tradition. It is, therefore, crucial that we make a succinct historical inspection of this notion in its various manifestations prior to Whitehead. II. Process Metaphysics Against any anti-metaphysical tendencies of his era, Whitehead tried to make a “dispassionate consideration of the nature of things, antecedently to any special investigation into their details. Such a standpoint is termed metaphysical.”17 This explains why he developed a comprehensive metaphysical system for the understanding of science, society and self as found in his major texts. He referred to this project as “Speculative Philosophy”. He defines speculative philosophy or metaphysics metaphysics as the endeavor to discover the general ideas that are indispensable to the analysis ofeverything that happens. In fact, Whatever is found in ‘practice’ must lie within the scope of metaphysical description. When the description fails to include the ‘practice,’ the metaphysics is inadequate and requires revision. “Metaphysics is nothing but the description of the generalities which applies to all the details of practice.”18In other words, it is: The endeavour to frame a coherent, logical, necessary system of general ideas in terms of which every element of another; ‘Quantum Mechanics’ studies the behaviour of unobservable subatomic particles such as electrons and photons, and their movements. Cfr. A. CHAKRAVARTTY, Metaphysics for Scientific Realism, New York, Cambridge University Press USA 2007, p. 72. 13 J. MONSERRAT, Alfred N. Whitehead on Process Philosophy and Theology: Cosmos and Kenosis of Divinity ‘in’ Pensamiento, Vol. 64 (2008), num. 242, pp. 823-824. 14Cf., ROTH, R.,American Religious Philosophy, USA 1967, p. 123 15WHITEHEAD, A. N., Modes of Thought, p. 217 in Roth, R., American Religious Philosophy, USA 1967, p. 123 16WHITEHEAD, A. N., Modes of Thought, p. 16 in Roth, R., American Religious Philosophy, USA 1967, p. 123 17WHITEHEAD, A. N., Science and the Modern World, p.158. 18WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 13. our experience can be interpreted. By this notion of 'interpretation' I mean that everything of which we are conscious, as enjoyed, perceived, willed, or thought, shall have the character of a particular instance of the general scheme. Thus the philosophical scheme should be coherent, logical and, in respect of its interpretation, applicable and adequate.19 An adequate metaphysics then must apply in general terms to the whole of reality, including all human subjective experiences. Even though Whitehead’s metaphysics is especially constructed with reference to the emerging objective scientific worldview, he did not neglect subjective human experience. Indeed, the metaphysics is such that the normal uses of the terms subjective and objective no longer apply. This is because “nothing must be omitted, experience drunk and experience sober”.20 It is not adequate to construct a metaphysics that renders the full spectrum of the emotional and imaginative life invisible or insignificant. Whitehead warns that “philosophy may not neglect the multifariousness of the world—the fairies dance, and Christ is nailed to the cross”.21 Note that while Whitehead references fantastic inventions of human imagination, his objective is objectivity. A general description of reality is the goal. Process metaphysics views the structure of reality as one of change and process. All entities in the world possess processes and are contributing to a larger process, reality.Process metaphysics is concerned with what exists in the world and with what terms this reality is to be understood. The guiding force behind this concept is that reality is to be explained in terms of processes andnot static Aristotelian substances. For process metaphysicians, change of all sorts is the predominant quality of reality. Whitehead’s process metaphysics “is concerned with the becoming, the being and the relatedness of actual entities.” In his metaphysics, “relatedness is dominant over quality. All relatedness has its foundation in relatedness of actualities.”22 Hence, in the Whiteheadian categorical scheme, relatedness takes priority just as the Aristotelian substance does in Aristotle’s scheme. In his definition of process metaphysics above, Whitehead suggests that a conceptual scheme can be necessary and appropriate to the interpretation of experience. Thisis his most important claim, for it is this which enables him to frame an ontology which includes all that there is.Yet any such relation of necessity and contingency seems to present itself as a dilemma. Leslie Armour puts the dilemma as follows: The claim that there must be some necessary truths arises chiefly from the association of necessity and constancy. If experiences are to be explained, something must remain constant throughout the sequence to be explained. If there are no necessities in reality, it is not certain that anything will be or has been constant. Yet Whitehead was convinced that our experience is Heraclitean: The most basic and important category is that of events. In such a universe, 19Ibid., p. 3. 20WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Adventures of Ideas, 226 21WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 338. 22WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. xiii. International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 245 nothing stays the same. Every actuality seems contingent. The conflict between flux and explanation is perhaps the oldest element in western metaphysics. One can read Plato as struggling to reconcile Parmenides who seemed to have discovered the logical conditions for intelligibility, and Heraclitus, who grasped the truth about experience.23 Not unnaturally, therefore, Whitehead saw all of subsequent philosophy as a series of struggles with Plato’s problems and insights.24 And he insisted that the abandonment ofthis quest was a major disaster. III. The Method of Process Metaphysics In his metaphysical endeavour, Heidegger does not undertake a book-burning campaign as Hume did nor does he launch a devastating attack on metaphysics as Kant. On reading historically backward, however, he asserts that in its historical journey, something went wrong with metaphysics. For Heidegger, this something that went wrong was the Seinsvergessnheit(forgetfulness) of Being.25 Heidegger, as a result, took it upon himself as a major task to return metaphysics from the derailment it had undergone over the years. Following this same approach like Heidegger, Whitehead constructs his metaphysical system with the following “strong impressions” dominating his mind: First, that the movement of historical, and philosophical, criticism of detached questions, which on the whole has dominated the last two centuries, has done its work and requires to be supplemented by a more sustained effort of constructive thought. Secondly, that the true method of philosophical construction is to frame a scheme of ideas, the best that one can, and unflinchingly to explore the interpretation of experience in terms of that scheme.26 Whitehead is conscious of the fact that despite the demise of classical metaphysics, his system, which is intended to be a modification of the former, is not final and error free. He expresses this consciousness when he states that “in philosophical discussion, the merest hint of dogmatic certainty as to finality of statement is an exhibition of folly.”27 The best method of metaphysics, according to Whitehead, is by way of descriptive generalization which involves the fusion of empiricism and rationalism. In his definition of speculative philosophy Whitehead says that it must be “applicable” and “adequate”. And he defines these thus: “here ‘applicable’ means that some items of experience are thus interpretable and ‘adequate’ means that there are no items incapable of such interpretation.”28 Empiricism then resides in its appeal to experience since we can deal only with what we experience and as such we must turn to such experience to determine the validity of what we speculate or theorize 23LESLIE ARMOUR.,Whitehead’s Metaphysics,Process Studies, Vol. 21, Number 4, Winter, 1992.pp. 203. 24For Whitehead, “the safest general characterisation of European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato” Process and Reality, p. 39. 25HEIDEGGER, M., Basic Problems of Phenomenology, Indiana: IndianaUniversity Press, 1982, pp. 17, 120, 319. 26WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. xiv. 27Ibid. 28A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 3. about.29 In the words of Whitehead, “the ultimate appeal into the general consciousness of what in practice we experience.”30 Yet this empiricism alone cannot give us metaphysical knowledge since, as Whitehead says, “the collapse of the method of rigid empiricism… occurs whenever we seek larger generalities.”31 The method of descriptive generalization involves “an accent from a particular fact, or from a species to the genus exemplified.”32 The genus exemplified refers to the larger generalities and only rationalism can elicit these larger generalities. But is this method of descriptive generalisation a form of induction? The answer is affirmative but only in the broad sense of the term given that in Whitehead’s estimation, there is no strict enumeration of particular facts. Yet, as Whitehead puts it, where observation (empiricism) fails, imagination takes over (hence imaginative rationalism). Contrary to the general understanding of induction, Whitehead does not conceive induction to be the derivation of general laws, instead it is the elicitation of definite features of experience. In his Science and the Modern World Whitehead holds that “the very baffling task of applying reason to elicit the general characteristics of the immediate occasion as set before us in direct cognition, is a necessary preliminary, if we are to justify induction.”33 The focus then is on the immediate occasion in its present concreteness. Thus, “the key to the process of induction”, Whitehead says, “is to be found in the right understanding of the immediate occasion of knowledge in its full concreteness.”34 Descriptive generalisation, then, is the “utilisation of specific notions, applying to a restricted group of facts, for the divination of the generic notions which apply to all facts.”35 These ‘specific notions’ are those arrived at by the process of imaginative rationalism. By introducing this notion of imaginative rationalism Whitehead hoped to solve what he perceived as “a somewhat more complex process than Bacon anticipated”36 in his (Bacon) treatment of induction. Whitehead believes that “what Bacon omitted”, in his theory of induction, “was the play of a free imagination, controlled by the requirements of coherence and logic.”37 Bacon’s weakness, according to Whitehead, was that “he had in mind the belief that with a sufficient care in the collection of instances, the general law would stand out of itself.” Whitehead, however, praises Bacon as “one of the great builders who constructed the mind of the modern world.”38 For Whitehead, metaphysics must begin from an empirical observation and then move to imaginative rationalism to form generalisations. In this same light, Jay Tidmarsh explains: Thus, any work in metaphysics must, as an initial matter, be strictly empirical. We must begin with that which we know, 29A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Adventures of Ideas, p. 223. Also, A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 300. 30A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 20. 31Ibid., p.7. 32 A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Adventures of Ideas, 235. 33A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Science and the Modern World,p. 44. 34Ibid. 35A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 8. 36A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Science and the Modern World,p. 44. 37A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 54. 38A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Science and the Modern World,p. 44. International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 246 and that which we know lies entirely within our human experience. Then from that empirical basis we can attempt to generalize to those aspects of experience in which the totality of the Universe shares. These universal aspects of existence then lead us to establish a working hypothesis about the nature of existence. Next, we can test the hypothesis against additional empirical evidence in order to determine whether the hypothesis adequately explains the real world. If all aspects of our actual world can be explained bythe hypothesis, then the hypothesis is validated on the basis of existing knowledge; but if some aspects of the world escape its explanatory reach, then the hypothesis must fail.39 In his Alfred North Whitehead, N. Pittenger summarizes Whitehead’s method of descriptive generalisation in the same vein as Tidmarsh: It is empirical in that it begins from the most careful study of some given, perhaps quite restricted area. This may be science in any of its branches; it may be religious experience or moral awareness or the realm of the ‘aesthetic’. But also rational, for from these careful study of particular areas, generalisations are made.40 Whitehead’s Process metaphysics as such employs three methodologies, usually simultaneously: empiricism (knowledge from experience), rationalism (knowledge from deduction), and speculation (knowledge from imagination). Whitehead’s famous metaphor for philosophy is that of a short airplane flight: The true method of discovery is like the flight of an aeroplane. It starts from the ground of particular observation; it makes a flight in the thin air of imaginative generalization; and it again lands for renewed observation rendered acute by rational interpretation.41 Philosophy begins on the ground with the concrete reality of lived experience. Experience provides us with the raw data for our theories. Then, our thought takes off, losing contact with the ground and soaring into heights of imaginative speculation. During speculation, we use rational criteria and imagination to synthesize facts into a (relatively) systematic worldview. In the end, however, our theories must eventually land and once again make contact with the ground—our speculations and hypotheses must ultimately answer once again to the authority of experience. By taking this airplane flight as a model for speculative metaphysics, Whitehead envisions the process of metaphysics to consist in an unending series of “test flights,” as our metaphysical conclusions are never final and always hypothetical. The process of adjusting our metaphysics to meet the demands of experience is a task with no end in sight, as experience continually provides the philosopher with new facts. Thus, process metaphysics regards the status of its own claims as contingent and tentative. In the words of Whitehead, “metaphysical categories are not dogmatic statements of the obvious; they are tentative formulations of the ultimate 39J. TIDMARSH, “Whitehead’s Metaphysics and the Law: A Dialogue” (1998). Scholarly Works.Paper 24, htt://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship/24, (page consulted on 25th September 2015), Pdf doc, 6 – 7. 40N. Pittenger, Alfred North Whitehead, London: Lurtherworth Press, 1969, p. 18. 41A. N. WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 5. generalities.”42 This differs significantly from classical metaphysical systems, which are regarded as final, authoritative, and necessary.43 For Bergson, metaphysics is the fruit of intuition. As Monserrat explains, “it was an intuition of the profound nature of vital movement by way of immediate experience. It is an intuition that perceives life as duration of a continuous future.”44Stumpf quotes Bergson in these words: To think intuitively is to think in duration…. Intuition starts from movement, posits it, or rather perceives it as reality itself, and sees in immobility only an abstract moment, a snapshot taken by our mind…. Intuition bound up to a duration which is growth, perceives in it an uninterrupted continuity of unforeseeable novelty; it sees, it knows that the mind draws from the more than it has, that spirituality consists in just that, and that reality, impregnated with spirit, creation.45 Whitehead also thought that metaphysics was born out of intuition. However, he thought it was an intuition based on experience. Metaphysics is thus reached by way of intuition. It comes from experience as from the perception of ones own body in an objective world that is organically open. Nevertheless, while philosophy is based on intuitive experience, it is something more: it is a rational and reflective construction of general concepts that are applied to the understanding of all concrete situations; in addition, they give meaning to précised and particular knowledge whether it is in daily life or in the sciences. For J. Monserrat, metaphysics may be arrived at intuitively but it is not formulated without rational and philosophical reflection. Metaphysics, for Whitehead is an abstraction that tries to create universal concepts that are general and cover all possible manifestations of reality. Hence four factors were present in Whitehead’s conception of metaphysics: first, intuition, based on experience, of the organic self in the world (in this case, it is true that metaphysics was born out of experiential intuition); second, his knowledge of the surprising scientific image of the world in the beginning years of quantum mechanics; third his knowledge of the authors that were trying to formulate the general concepts of a new metaphysics that integrated this experiential intuition with modern science (Bergson, Pierce or James); fourth, his original elaboration of a system of concepts that allowed the integration of all of our ordinary, religious and scientific experiences in a unified metaphysics.46 Is Whitehead then an empiricist or a rationalist? The answer is both. His aim is to reconcile both schools of thought. He follows in the footsteps of the British empiricists in opposing those thinkers who insist that metaphysics is a process of apriori deduction from incontestable first premises. At the 42A. N.,WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. 8. 43CF., Process Philosophy, in Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy 44J., MONSERRAT,“Alfred n. Whitehead on Process Philosophy and Theology: Cosmos and Kenosis of Divinity”p. 826. 45BERGSON, H., as quoted by Stumpf, S. E., Philosophy: History and Problems,p. 413. 46J.,MONSERRAT,“Alfred n. Whitehead on Process Philosophy and Theology: Cosmos and Kenosis of Divinity”pp. 827-828. International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 247 same time, Whitehead is a rationalist for he recognizes the role of reason in generalizing from initial observation to universal experience.47 In fact, in the preface to Process and Reality, Whitehead observes that his philosophy is based upon a recurrence to that phase of philosophic thought which began with Descartes and ended with Hume. The philosophic scheme which they endeavour to explain is termed the Philosophy of Organism. There is no doctrine put forward which cannot cite in its defence some explicit statement of one of this group of thinkers, or of one of the two founders of all Western thought, Plato and Aristotle. But the philosophy of organism is apt to emphasize just those elements in the writings of these masters which subsequent systematizers have put aside. The writer who most fully anticipated the main positions of the philosophy of organism is John Locke in his Essay, especially in its later books.48 From his definition of metaphysics, it is evident that Whitehead’s insistence on a coherent and logical metaphysics on the one hand, and on an applicable and adequate one on the other, demonstrates his desire to bridge the gap separating rationalists from empiricists in modern philosophical discourse. 49 IV. The Categoreal Scheme Whitehead developed a set of categories to elucidate his whole theorising on reality. These are: the categories of the Ultimate, categories of Existence, Explanation and Obligation. For him, every entity should be a specific instance of one category of existence, every explanation should be a specific instance of categories of explanation, and every obligation should be a specific instance of the categoreal obligation. The category of the Ultimate expresses the general principle presupposed in the three more special categories.50It would be necessary to systematize the, more radical, fundamental metaphysical concepts that permit the understanding of the real world, both for the natural person and the scientist. It is clear that the metaphysical concepts created by Whitehead looked to be congruent with the images of the real world in science. Actual Entities Part of the philosophical task is to identify what kinds of things exist. Of course, that depends on what the philosopher means by exist. For some thinkers, to exist means to be fully actual as a concrete particular. For Kierkegaard, the term existence is reserved for an individual human being. To exist, he said, “implies being a certain kind of individual, an individual who strives, who considers alternatives, who chooses, who decides, and who above all, makes a commitment.”51 Whitehead reserves the mode of existence for what is actual and here he talks of actual entities. This is, without doubt, Whitehead’s most basic concept. For him: 47J. TIDMARSH, “Whitehead’s Metaphysics and the Law: A Dialogue”, p. 7. 48A. N. WHITEHEAD, Process and Reality, p. xi. 49J. TIDMARSH, “Whitehead’s Metaphysics and the Law: A Dialogue”, p. 8. 50WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, pp. 20-21. 51Kierkegaard in Stumpf, S. E., Philosophy: History and Problems,New York, McGraw-Hill, 2003, pp. 357. ‘Actual entities’ – also termed ‘actual occasions’52- are the final real things of which the world is made up. There is no going behind actual entities to find anything more real. They differ among themselves: God is an actual entity and so is the most trivial puff of existence in far off empty space. But though there are gradations of importance, and diversities of function, yet in the principles which actuality exemplifies all are on the same level. The final facts are, all alike, actual entities; ….53 Like the atoms of Democritus they are microcosmic entities, aggregates of which, termed societies or nexus, form the macrocosmic entities of our everyday experience - trees, houses, people. But whereas the atoms of Democritus are inert, imperishable, material stuff, Whitehead's actual entities are vital, transient “drops of experience, complex and interdependent.”54 To hold that the final real things of which the world is made up are drops of experience is not to imply that consciousness permeates inanimate nature; for consciousness can characterize only extremely sophisticated actual entities, and actual entities have the potentiality for the sophistication productive of consciousness only when they are members of extremely complex societies such as the society we call the human brain.55 Actual entities, then, are units of process, and the title Process and Reality is meant to indicate that for Whitehead these microcosmic units of process are the final realities - since there is no going behind actual entities to find anything more real. On the other hand, to mistakenly consider an aggregate of actual entities as a final reality is to commit the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness.56 This is because for him, “the actual world is a process, and that the process is the becoming of actual entities. Thus actual entities are creatures.”57 Eternal Objects From a Whiteheadian perspective, entities can be actual (real things that exist) or ideal (pure forms that do not exist 52For all practical purposes the phrases actual occasion and actual entity are interchangeable. Whitehead notes only one difference: the word occasion implies a spatio-temporal location. God is the one nontemporal actual entity. Hence Whitehead observes that “the term 'actual occasion' will always exclude God from its scope” (Process and Reality, p.88). It is true, however, that even though “the term 'actual occasion' is used synonymously with ‘actual entity’” (Process Reaity, p. 77), the use of actual occasion should alert one to the likelihood that the “character of extensiveness has some direct relevance to the discussion, either extensiveness in the form of temporal extensiveness, that is to say ‘duration,’ or extensiveness in the form of spatial extension, or in the more complete signification of spatio-temporal extensiveness” (Process Reality, p. 77). 53WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 18. 54Ibid. 55SHERBURNE,D.W.,A Key to Whitehead's Process and Reality (Macmillan, 1966), quoted by Alan AndersonWhiteheadian Terminology at http://websyte.com/alan/termin.htm (page consulted on the 1st September 2011) 56For Whitehead, this is “merely the accidental error of mistaking the abstract for the concrete.” Science and the Modern World, p. 52. 57WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 22. International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 248 but are able to define existent realities). These ideal entities are known as eternal objects. They define a realm of possibilities, of conditional potentials of existent reality and therefore of actual entities and their dynamic processes of association in their complex evolution. There is a terminological diversity that revolves around this concept: forms, ideal identities, abstract entities, universals, potential forms.58 For Whitehead, “any entity whose conceptual recognition does not involve a necessary reference to any definite actual entities of the temporal world is called an ‘eternal object’.”59 Eternal objects are forms of definiteness capable of specifying the character of actual entities; they are “Pure Potentials for the Specific Determination of Fact.”60 An actual entity's process of becoming is a process of acquiring definiteness by a series of decisions to select or reject various forms of definiteness (eternal objects) after grading them in a diversity of relevance.61In describing the three formative elements of the universe (creativity, eternal objects and God) Whitehead maintains that eternal objects are “the realm of ideal entities, or forms, which are in themselves not actual, but are such that they are exemplified in everything that is actual, according to some proportion of relevance.”62 That’s why an eternal object can be described only in terms of its potentiality for ‘ingression’ into the becoming of actual entities.63 The selection and rejection of eternal objects is the done only by each actual entity since eternal objects are simply pure potentials. Hence, “an eternal object is always a potentiality for actual entities; but in itself, as conceptually felt, it is neutral as to the fact of its physical ingression in any particular actual entity of the temporal world.”64 In this light, Christian explains: Eternal objects are pure potentials. They are in fundamental contrast with actual entities. In themselves they do not determine in what actual entities they are ingredient. This is what is meant by saying that they are “pure” potentials. They are merely possible forms of definiteness. Prehensions of eternal objects are called conceptual prehensions, in contrast with prehensions of actual entities, which are called physical prehensions. 65 But how free are actual entities in their decisions? Not entirely for as Sherburne explains that any given actual entity does not make its decisions with utter freedom.66For 58MONSERRAT J., p. 829. 59WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 44. 60Ibid. p. 22. 61Cf., ibid., p. 43. 62WHITEHEAD, A. N., Religion in the Making,New York: Macmillan, 1926, p. 24. 63WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 23. The term ‘ingression’ refers to the particular mode in which the potentiality of an eternal object is realized in a particular actual entity, contributing to the definiteness of that actual entity. 64WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 44. 65CHRISTIAN, W. A.An Interpretation of Whitehead's Metaphysics, Yale, 1959, p.13. The terms Conceptual prehension and Physical prehensions shall be explained below when talking about Prehension 66SHERBURNE,D.W.,A Key to Whitehead's Process and Reality (Macmillan, 1966), quoted by Alan AndersonWhiteheadian Whitehead, “an actual entity arises from decisions for it and by its very existence provides decisions for other actual entities which supersede it.”67 The past, from which it inherits, presents it with certain forms of definiteness that it is compelled to reiterate.Actual entities, however, exercise much freedom in their selection of eternal objects. Furthermore, eternal objects are essentially aloof from change in that it is of their essence to be eternal. But they are involved in change in the sense that the very process of “becoming in any given actual occasion is the process of determining, via selected eternal objects, the specific character, the kind of definiteness that will make that actual entity what it will be.”68 Hence for Whitehead, “the things which are temporal arise by their participation in the things which are eternal.”69 Creativity Whitehead argues that the best description of ultimate reality is through the principle of creativity. Creativity is the universal of universals - that which is only actual in virtue of its accidents or instances. Creativity is the most general notion at the base of all that actually exists. Thus, all actual entities, even God, are in a sense “creatures” of creativity.70 For J. R. Wilcox: Creativity in Whitehead is analogous to prime matter in Aristotle in that it is the counterpart of form. As the "ultimate notion of the highest generality at the base of actuality," it is "without a character of its own" and "cannot be characterized because all characters are more special than itself" (PR 20/30). Creativity is the "ultimate behind all forms" (PR 20/30). There is, however, a crucial difference between creativity and prime matter in that whereas prime matter is passive with respect to receiving the actuality of the forms, creativity is pure activity. Creativity is "divested of the notion of passive receptivity, either of ‘form’ or of external relation" (PR 31/46). For Whitehead, it is not the material, but the formal principle that is passive or potential; the "eternal objects are the pure potentials of the universe" (PR 149/226).71 In Religion in the Making, creativity is the process “whereby the actual world has its character of temporal passage to novelty”72 while in Process and Reality, “creativity is the universal of universals characterizing ultimate matter of fact….Creativity is the principle of novelty.”73 For W. Christian,Creativity is Whitehead's term for the most fundamental character of actuality. Creativity is not an individual thing and has no status apart from actual Terminology at http://websyte.com/alan/termin.htm (page consulted on the 1st September 2011) 67WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 68. 68SHERBURNE,D.W.,A Key to Whitehead's Process and Reality 69WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 40. 70HUSTWIT, J. R.,Process Philosophyin Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy at http://www.iep.utm.edu/processp/ (pageconsulted on the 20th September 2011). 71WILCOX, J. R., A Monistic Interpretation of Whitehead’s Creativity, in ProcessStudies, Vol. 20, Number 3, Fall, 1991, p. 163. (PR is an abbreviation of Whitehead’s Process and Reality) 72WHITEHEAD, A. N., Religion in the Making,p. 24. 73WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 21. International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 249 entities.74In Whitehead’s system, the ultimacy of creativity is undisputed. For him: In all philosophic theory there is an ultimate which is actual in virtue of its accidents. It is only then capable of characterisation through its accidental embodiments, and apart from these accidents is devoid of actuality. In the philosophy of organism this ultimate is termed ‘creativity’; and God is its primordial, non-temporal accident.75 Concrescence For Whitehead, concrescence is the name for the process in which the “universe of many things acquires an individual unity in a determinate relegation of each item of the ‘many’ to its subordination in the constitution of the novel ‘one’.”76 Cobb explains that concrescence is simply the process of becoming “concrete.” Concrete here means fully actual as a completed actual occasion.77Iroegbu looks at the term from an etymological perspective: Concrescence is the act of becoming of actual entities. From the Latin Concrescere, to grow together, it is the productive act, the act of becoming of a being which is togetherness. In concrescence, the new being passes from its components in their ideal disjunctive diversity into the same components in their realised concrete togetherness. The new being becomes real.78 For Monserrat, this term comes from the vocabulary of biology: It is the union and the growing together of parts that were originally separate. It is the constitution of unity in the universe of multiple things until the final result of a new unitary entity. The evolutionary process of the universe has been a process of concrescence because the original actual entities are dynamic and produce a process that is made up of continual relationships between entities.79 Concrescence is, therefore, the growing together of a many into the unity of a one.With the attaining of its satisfaction an actual entity is completed and perishes, that is, it becomes a datum for fresh instances of concrescence. Cobb explains further: the use of the term “concrescence” places emphasis on the idea that even these momentary flashes of actuality that Whitehead calls actual occasions are processes. There is the actual occasion in the process of becoming, and then there is the completed occasion. Whitehead calls the completion “satisfaction.” For Cobb, this term emphasizes that this process of becoming is characterised by subjectivity. There is a subjective aim, a subjective form, a decision and a satisfaction. But as soon as the occasion attains satisfaction it becomes an objective datum for successor occasions.80 74CHRISTIAN, W. A.An Interpretation of Whitehead's Metaphysics, Yale, 1959, p.13 75WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 7. 76Ibid., p. 211. 77J. B. COBB, JR., A Glossary with Alphabetical Index, p. 59. 78IROEGBU, P., Metaphysics: The Kpim of Philosophy, Nigeria, International Universities Press Ltd, 1995, p.24 79MONSERRAT J., p. 829. 80J. B. COBB, JR., A Glossary with Alphabetical Index, p. 59. Prehension Concrescence describes a genetic process in which multiple things in the universe organically unify. Prehension is a term that describes the activity of each of the actual entities when they make a concretion or unit with other entities. The unity of the universe is constructed by way of the prehension of entities upon others. It is the active essence of the actual entity: to be dynamic in a process that configures the concrescent unit with other entities.81For Whitehead, every prehension consists of three factors: (a) the ‘subject’ which is prehending, namely, the actual entity in which that prehension is a concrete element; (b) the ‘datum’ which is prehended; (c) the ‘subjective form’ which is how that subject prehens that datum.82 In the simplest case, we have a prehension of a single actual occasion, so that the objective datum is the aspect of that occasion that is prehended. But the datum of most prehensions is a nexus. For example, especially in conscious experience, I prehend a stone, not the individual molecules of which it consists, much less the individual quanta. And the objective datum of the occasion as a whole is always a nexus, namely, the actual world of the occasion. Whitehead further notes two different types of prehensions depending on the type of entity involved: Prehensions of actual entities – that is, prehensions whose data involve actual entities – are termed ‘physical prehensions’; and prehensions of eternal objects are termed ‘conceptual prehensions.’… There are two species of prehensions: (a) ‘positive prehensions’ which are termed ‘feelings,’ and (b) ‘negative prehensions’ which is said to ‘eliminate from feeling.’83 These are just some of concepts in Whitehead’s process metaphysics. Conclusion As is evident from the above presentation, Process metaphysics is characterized by an attempt to reconcile the diverse intuitions found in human experience into a coherent holistic scheme. Hustwit explains that this reconciliation of the intuitions of objectivity and subjectivity, with a concern for scientific findings, produces the explicitly metaphysical speculation that the world, at its most fundamental level, is made up of momentary events of experience rather than enduring material substances. Process metaphysics speculates that these momentary events, called actual occasions or actual entities, are essentially self-determining, experiential, and internally related to each other.Actual occasions correspond to electrons and sub-atomic particles, but also to human persons. The human person is a society of billions of these occasions (that is, the body), which is organized and coordinated by a single dominant occasion (that is, the mind). Thus, process philosophy avoids a strict mind-body dualism.84 Whitehead’s process metaphysics does not rely on the usual dualisms that have vexed previous metaphysical systems. We no longer need to be troubled about the distinctions 81MONSERRAT J., p. 830. 82WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 24. 83WHITEHEAD, A. N.,Process and Reality, p. 24. 84HUSTWIT, J. R.,Process Philosophyin Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) @ www.ijtsrd.com eISSN: 2456-6470 @ IJTSRD | Unique Paper ID – IJTSRD29982 | Volume – 4 | Issue – 2 | January-February 2020 Page 250 between matter and mind, animate and inanimate, created and evolved, nature and nurture, or reductionism and emergence. The difference between atoms, animals, artifacts, and humans is in the degrees of complexity, the intensity of causal relationships, and the extent of self-creative freedom integrated in these various phenomena. The differences are not in any essentialized notions of natural kinds. Most philosophical problems in the metaphysics of contemporary science disappear with Whitehead’s event-centered process philosophy.85 In sum, Whitehead’s process metaphysics holds a unitary view of the world, that is, one order theory of the world. The world is conceived as an integrated and inter-related web of spatio-temporal processes. Every entity in the world is included in a single order of happenings. There is no exception, not even God as we shall see in the next chapter. As such, reality is organic and inter-related. Once static substance is negated, and along with it a model of fixed parts associated mechanically and externally, process thought takes up the model of mutually interdependent parts associated organically. Nature, including both organic and inorganic entities, in this view, becomes a vast complex of interacting forces and therefore no longer is it the independent essence or substance of which an entity is constituted-but rather the relation of that entity with others that determines the nature and mode of its existence. This leads to what can be called a social view of reality. This of course is vital in a time when there is a universal search for a genuinely social conception of man, and reality as a whole, Whitehead can speak of God in organic relation with the world. BIBLIOGRAPHY [1] COBB,J.B. (2008),-A Glossary with Alphabetical Index to Technical Terms in Process and Reality: Whitehead Word Book, P&F Press, Claremont. [2] (1965), A Christian Natural Theology (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press. [3] COBB, J.B. & GRIFFIN, D.R. (1976), Process Theology: an Introductory Exposition; The Westminster Press. [4] CHRISTIAN, W.A. (1959), An Interpretation of Whitehead's Metaphysics, New Haven: Yale University Press. [5] HARTSHORNE,C. (1972),Whitehead’s Philosophy: Selected Essays, 1935-70, Lincoln, University of Nebraska Press. [6] JOHNSON, A.H. (1962),Whitehead’s Theory of Reality., Dover Publications. [7] KUNTZ,P.G. (1984),Alfred North Whitehead, G. K. Hall & Company. [8] LOWE, V. (1962), Understanding Whitehead, Baltimore: John Hopkins Press. [9] MARTIN, R.M. (1974), Whitehead’s Categoreal Scheme and Other Papers, MartinusNijhoff, The Hague. [10] MAYS, W. (1977),Whitehead’s Philosophy of Science and Metaphysics, The Hague: MartinusNijhoff. [11] MESLE, Robert (2008), Process-Relational Philosophy: An Introduction to Alfred North Whitehead, Pennsylvania: 85Cf.,GRASSIE, W.,Resources and Problems in Whitehead's Metaphysics, Templeton Foundation Press. [12] PITTENGER, N. (1969), Alfred North Whitehead, London: Lurtherworth Press. [13] RESCHNER, N. (2000), - Process Philosophy: A Survey of Basic Issues, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. [14] (1996), Process Metaphysics: An Introduction to Process Philosophy, New York: State University of New York Press. [15] SCHILPP, Paul Arthur (ed.) (1991), The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead, volume III of The Library of Living Philosophers.Open Court, La Salle, Illionis, 2. Edition. [16] STENGERS,I. (2002), Penser avec Whitehead: une libre et sauvage création de concepts, Paris: Seuil. [17] SWEET, W., “Introduction: Taking Metaphysics Seriously” in Approaches to Metaphysics, W. Sweet, (ed.), Kluwer Academic Publishers, New York 2004, 1- 2. [18] HUSTWIT, J., “Process Philosophy” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy online at http://plato.stanford.edu (consulted on 25th March [19] FORD, L.S., “A Guide to Whitehead” in Teaching Philosophy, Vol. 7, No. 2, April 1984, 143. [20] ZVIE BAR-ON, A., The Categories and the Principle of Coherence: Whitehead’s Theory of Categories in Historical Perspective, Dordrecht: MartinusNijhoff Publishers, 1987. [21] USHENKO, A.P., The Philosophy of Relativity, London: G. Allen &Unwin, Ltd., 1937. [22] IROEGBU, P., Metaphysics: The Kpim of Philosophy, Nigeria, International Universities Press Ltd, 1995. [23] HEIDEGGER M., - Being and Time, J. MACQUARRIE – E. ROBINSON (trs.), Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1962, 23. [24] An Introduction to Metaphysics, Yale University Press Inc., London 1959 [25] Basic Problems of Phenomenology, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1982. [26] TIDMARSH,J.,“Whitehead’s Metaphysics and the Law: A Dialogue” (1998). Scholarly Works. Paper 24, online at htt://scholarship.law.nd.edu/law_faculty_scholarship/ 24, (page consulted on 25th September 2015), Pdf doc, 6 – 7. [27] LOWE, V., “The Development of Whitehead’s Philosophy” in The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead, P. A. Schilpp (ed), Northwestern University Press, 1941. [28] LESLIE ARMOUR, “Whitehead’s Metaphysics”, in Process Studies, Vol. 21, Number 4, Winter, 1992. [29] Whitehead, A. North, Adventures of Ideas, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1947. [30] _________, Modes of Thought, New York: Free Press, 1966. [31] _________, Process and Reality, Corrected Edition, ed. Griffin & Sherburne, New York: The Free Press, 1978 [32] _____, Science and the Modern World, The New American Library of World literature, inc.New York, 1926. [33] ___________, Religion in the Making, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1930. View publication stats

Analysis: Critiques of Emergentism, Part 2


Analysis: Critiques of Emergentism
Part 2

What is the process philosophy according to Whitehead?
Whitehead's process philosophy argues that "there is urgency in coming to see the world as a web of interrelated processes of which we are integral parts, so that all of our choices and actions have consequences for the world around us."
How did process philosophy view reality?

Within ontology, the study of being, and metaphysics, the study of the nature of reality, there are two dominant schools of thought. Process philosophy is one of these schools, and it proposes that reality is made up of fluid and dynamic entities, always in the process of change.

Why is process philosophy important?

Process philosophy is one of the two dominant schools of thought in ontology and metaphysics and within philosophy in general. It is important as it provides another way to view the nature of reality. Rather than static matter, process philosophy proposes that things are processes and ever-changing.

What is process philosophy according to Whitehead?

Whitehead sees philosophy, especially process philosophy, as a bridge between disciplines. It is a way for various kinds of understanding to merge together, to give a fuller picture of the true nature of reality.

 

amazon link


The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion 1st Edition, by Philip Clayton (Editor), Paul Davies (Editor)

Much of the modern period was dominated by a `reductionist' theory of science. On this view, to explain any event in the world is to reduce it down to fundamental particles, laws, and forces. In recent years reductionism has been dramatically challenged by a radically new paradigm called `emergence'. According to this new theory, natural history reveals the continuous emergence of novel phenomena: new structures and new organisms with new causal powers. Consciousness is yet one more emergent level in the natural hierarchy. Many theologians and religious scholars believe that this new paradigm may offer new insights into the nature of God and God's relation to the world.

This volume introduces readers to emergence theory, outlines the major arguments in its defence, and summarizes the most powerful objections against it. Written by experts but suitable as an introductory text, these essays provide the best available presentation of this exciting new field and its potentially momentous implications.

* * * * * * *

REFERENCES


I
(Large) Excerpts from Philip Clayton and Paul Davis', The Re-Emergence of Emergence

II

Process Philosophy and the Emergent Theory of Mind: Whitehead, Lloyd Morgan and Schelling
Arran Gare
Concrescence 3:1-12 (2002) Copy BIBTEX

AbstractWhile some process philosophers have denigrated the emergent theory of mind, what they have denigrated has been ‘materialist’ theories of emergence. My contention is that one of the most important reasons for embracing process philosophy is that it is required to make intelligible the emergence of consciousness. There is evidence that this was a central concern of Whitehead. However, Whitehead acknowledged that his metaphysics was deficient in this regard. In this paper I will argue that to fully understand the emergent theory of mind and its relation to process philosophy it is necessary to recast the whole history of modern philosophy in terms of efforts by philosophers grappling with the relationship between mind and body, or more broadly, consciousness and nature. This will involve granting a central place to Schelling’s philosophy, the ideas that influenced it and how Schelling’s insights were developed by subsequent philosophers. Process philosophy will then be seen as the tradition generated by efforts to transcend the opposition between idealism and materialism, and its promise in this regard, apart from anything else, is what makes it the most promising philosophy for the future.

III

From Things to Events: Whitehead and the Materiality of Process

Abstract

The new materialist turn has refocused attention upon the shortcomings, both philosophical and scientific, of styles of thought that figure matter as an inert substance. According to the new materialists, the concept of matter must be rethought in order to account for its own vital capacities. Whilst largely sympathetic to this critique, this paper short-circuits the contemporary focus on matter through a sustained engagement with the process philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead. For Whitehead, the concept of matter represents a failure to think process on its own terms; that is, without invoking an underlying permanence. Whitehead's philosophy is thus of great significance to contemporary debates because it questions what it means to speak of agency, relation, and vitality in a world composed of processual events rather than things. In doing so, it sharpens our sensitivities towards nonhuman processes of existential change. Exploiting this capacity to shift our attention, the paper explores the implications of Whitehead's philosophy by staging an encounter with a peculiar experimental object. By unpacking the key concepts of ‘occasion’, ‘prehension’, and ‘concrescence’, the object in question is gradually transformed from discrete thing to processual event, with a number of consequences for materialist thought.

IV
Emergentist Panpsychism
by Philip Clayton
1PCTS, May 3-4, 2019  <-- go here to read

TRANSCRIPT

Panpsychism is not like pregnancy. A woman either is or is not pregnant. In such cases more generally, either x or not-x. By contrast, you are not either warm or not warm, tall or not tall, smart or not smart. You can be more or less slow, more or less prompt, more or less witty. The discussion of panpsychism is changed in important and fruitful ways when we recognize that the topic is better understood in the latter way than in the former. At first glance, the panpsychism debate appears to be a question of all or nothing, just as the thief either takes all William’s money or he doesn’t. But I suggest that we need to think our way beyond this way of approaching panpsychism. Particularly in the context of panentheism, our discussions should become more complex than, say, the thesis that all levels of evolution can be summarized under the heading of pan-psyche or, following David Ray Griffin, pan-experience. Instead, I will argue, the discussion of God, evolution, and psyche needs to be expanded to include the full variety of qualities, including awareness, intention, goal-directed behavior, mental representation, cognition, and consciousness. Clearly this shift has implications for understanding the nature and scope of metaphysics and theology, a topic to which I shall return at the end of this short paper. Three things will happen when we return to the panpsychism question after this analysis. The first, I hope, is that it will help to deepen the discussions of John Cobb’s work, and of Whitehead’s, during out two days together. The other two reflect my deep interest in biological evolution and theology. We should be able to specify the sense in which evolution produces qualities that were not actually already in the parts. And, finally, we should be able to reach a more complex understanding of the relevance of panentheism to questions of the evolution of consciousness, and hence a more complex understanding of the Divine itself. The upshot is a more limited affirmation of panpsychism, in contrast to the more “maximal” affirmation of the existence of psyche in all things, or all things as psyche. The qualities that we call mental or proto-mental are extremely diverse. Because the differences are greater than is often acknowledged, in this paper I will be defending a minimal or “gradualist” panpsychism rather than traditional or “maximal” panpsychism. It will not have escaped you that minimal and maximal are terms on a quantitative scale rather than expressions of a forced either/or choice. Panpsychism in this more minimal form, I will argue, is the more 2 compelling view; and the quantitative nature of the discussion should help us to more fully nuance our discussion during the discussion. First, though, let’s get a full sense of the range of questions raised by this topic. If we are going to make progress in the areas where stalemates usually arise in discussions between Whiteheadians and emergentists, we will need to understand the questions that need to be raised … and the questions that are less productive. Clarifying the questions (1) Mind and mental entities. Of course, many philosophers today doubt whether mentality as such even exists or, more accurately, whether mental states or qualia have a primary rather than derivative existence. Most people here, I assume, are well aware of this debate, and some engage in it professionally. But the major advocates of physicalism are not present here (as far as I know); in the audience I don’t see Wolf Singer, Francis Crick, or Dan Dennett. Whether anything mental exists may be a major debate, but I don’t think it’s the topic de jour. I thus recommend that we begin instead with the assumption that some mental attributes or things exist and exercise causality qua mental. (I will problematize “the mental” in a moment.) Mentality is not merely an epiphenomenon. It is not merely supervenient on physical states, nor is it merely a weakly emergent property of physical matter/energy, where all true causal forces reside. In short, we have more important fish to fry than reductionism. Leaving aside reductionism at the start will allow us to focus in on a different set of questions. For example: Does finite mentality arise at some point in cosmic evolution, such that it was not actually present at one point in time and then later was? If mentality is emergent, then must it always be linked to something physical, say a body? Do separate mental units, say souls, exist, or are they just multiple manifestations of one mental reality (call it God)? Skrbana puts it nicely: The central issue here is whether we speak of such mind as “mind of single universal” (God, the Absolute, the World Soul, and so on) or of mind as attributable to each thing in itself (of each object’s possessing its own unique, individual mind). The former view would be a monist concept of mind, the latter a pluralist concept.1 Whitehead’s famous notion of actual entities2 moves in the direction of radical pluralism. Assume for the moment that he is right and that an extremely large number of actual entities (AEs) exist. This requires us to think of each such moment of creative becoming as a distinct entity or occasion, existing on its own. Of course, one can be a radical pluralist in this way and 3 still hold that AEs are so interdependent that they are internally related (as I argued in a recent paper). That would mean a radical pluralism of psyches. Does the world contain anything that is non-mental, such as purely physical objects? I’d encourage you to resist this either/or frame; it leads too quickly to a simple syllogism: Some mental things exist. Nothing exists that is purely physical. Hence, all things are mental things. I will suggest that the more interesting discussion is of the varieties of mentality or “psychisms.” Interesting nuances of “psychism” surface when one explores options such as limited panpsychism, emergentist panpsychism, or the panpsychism of potentiality and actuality, as I do below. These nuances cause us to reflect on the differences, and thus on the status of the unifying concepts. To proceed in this way is to hypothesize that “the mental” is not an either/or quality, such that an entity either is mental (has the attribute of mentality) or isn’t. (For now I use “a mental entity” and “an entity that has mentality” interchangeably.) It is more fruitful to ask, “To what extent, and in what sense, is this entity mental?” (2) Panentheism. A series of questions arise at the intersection of panpsychism and panentheism. Some represent difficult challenges for classical panpsychism. If there is a plurality of mental entities, how is God related to each one? For Whitehead, each actual entity is an ultimate, not more dependent on God than God is on it. But actual entities could be dependent on God in a stronger way, existing only through the continuing will of God; or they could be real individual expressions of a single divine Spirit (this is the view of the Indian philosopher Ramanuja); or, following Spinoza, what we call individuals might merely be ways that the one divine substance is manifested in a particular time or place ― modes of the One. How would one decide between these options? Panentheism might also raise some critical questions for classical (pre-Whiteheadian) panpsychism. What is God’s relationship to finite mental entities if they are really present “all the way down”? If God lures even an electron, what does God lure it to do? Or does theological panpsychism instead support monism? That would mean that the psyches that seem to be in all things are actually just one psyche: the one mind of God, or Nous in Plotinus’s sense. For that matter, how would one distinguish finite “natural” mentality from infinite divine mentality? Can the one be within the other without compromising the integrity of either? Do classical 4 panpsychisms maintain that it’s the God question that supports the dichotomy either everything is mental or nothing is mental and, if so, why? In contrast, a gradualist panpsychism begins with the question To what extent, and in what sense, is a given entity mental? Formulating this question, one immediately recognizes that the relationships between panpsychism and panentheism are rather more complex than one might have thought. There are no simple entailments: one can be a panpsychist without being a panentheist, for example if one is a pantheist. Conversely, one can be a panentheist without being a panpsychist, for example if one holds that the world is God’s (material) body. Above all, gradualist panpsychism shifts the conversation in that one must now ask about the relationship between the panentheistic God and the whole history of emergent mentality. Emergent Mentality Gradualist panpsychism seeks a theory of consciousness that is consonant with the results and the methods of the sciences as well as with human phenomenal experience. Let’s call this a theory of emergent mentality. It’s the view that the particles and physical states of (say) macrophysics and physical chemistry do not manifest an actual mentality; they do not have intentions, for example. The first self-reproducing cell, by contrast, does have a primitive awareness of its environment. Increasing complexity across biological evolution brings more and more complex awareness, with human consciousness being the most advanced form of awareness that we have yet discovered. Emergent mentality as I use the term stands in contrast to Whitehead’s panpsychism or “panexperientialism.” Famously, Whitehead holds that all units of reality are occasions of creative becoming. Each actual (as opposed to merely potential) entity is thus its own center of experience. If given only a single argument to defend this view, Whiteheadian panpsychists will generally argue that mentality cannot come from something that is non-mental. But Whiteheadians are by no means the only philosophers who object to gradualist theories of mentality. All dualists do, as well as many neuroscientists who are drawn toward exclusively material explanations of thought and consciousness. So let’s call this particular critique the “no mind from matter” (NMfM) Objection. Thomas Nagel sometimes expresses a similar intuition as fundamental or “schematic” for him: “In its schematic, pre-Socratic way, this sort of monism attempts to recognize the mental as a physically irreducible part of reality.”3 I will argue that this intuition does not stand up to closer examination, at least not in this particular (non-theistic) form. Finally, I do not think that theism as such falsifies one option and verifies the other. It is not inconsistent for advocates of most (but not all) forms of theism to affirm either Whiteheadian 5 panpsychism or emergent mentality. But I do think that setting panentheism in dialogue with contemporary philosophy and science supports gradual over maximal panpsychism. The argument proceeds in four steps. (1) Evolutionary mentality and emergentist panpsychism The evolutionary evidence suggests the emergence of the various phenomena that we call mentality, a position often called emergentist panpsychism. Of the various forms of limited or gradualist panpsychism, this position is in my view the most convincing. Once again, it starts by challenging the assumption that all existing things either are or are not centers of experience. Limiting or conditioning the “pan” in panpsychism is an important part of making this case. Thomas Nagel is a famous anti-emergentist panpsychist. He argues, for example: The implausibility of the reductive program that is needed to defend the completeness of … naturalism provides a reason for trying to think of alternatives—alternatives that make mind, meaning, and value as fundamental as matter and space-time in an account of what it. The fundamental elements of physics and chemistry have been inferred to explain the behavior of the inanimate world. Something more is needed to explain how there can be conscious, thinking creatures whose bodies and brains are composed of those elements. … Everything, living or not, is constituted from elements having a nature that is both physical and nonphysical—that is, capable of combining into mental wholes. So this reductive account can also be described as a form of panpsychism.4 Nagel and I agree in opposing the reduction to physicalism but disagree concerning when this “something more” is needed. He thinks that, in order to beat physicalism, mind must be fundamental to all things, whereas I argue that the first time it becomes fundamental is in the role it must play to explain self-reproducing cells. From cells on we no longer disagree. For the emergentist panpsychist, “mind” ― in the minimal form of awareness and goal-directed behavior ― is first discernible with the emergence of self-reproducing life; as a concept it only begins to play a role after that. From the birth of cellular agents, the two positions walk side by side. For example, both Godehard Brüntrup5 and I agree that unicellular organisms possess a rudimentary form of awareness. This awareness is a matter of life and death to the cell. After all, cells can live and reproduce, or they can die. From an evolutionary point of view, they have an interest in living. To move up a glucose gradient and receive more nutrition is in the interest of a unicellular organism; it is “good.” To move toward a toxin is “bad.” The cell’s (chemically mediated) awareness of its environment, which differentiates between the two, is of its very essence. 6 It’s fascinating to trace the evolutionary process from primitive awareness and goal-directed behavior at the birth of the biosphere to the most complex conscious cognition and subjective experiences. Note that, once a certain threshhold is passed, the anti-emergentist panpsychist appears to be as willing as the emergentist panpsychist to affirm the emergence of ever more complex mental phenomena. (2) Mind in potentia The more plausible the transition from potential to actual mentality becomes, the more the NMfM Objection is undercut. Although in the end my argument will require a theological dimension, the first step of the argument can be made without it. Although each cell is aware, each can potentially become part of (say) a human being, a being with the attribute of consciousness. So the cell is potentially conscious if the right circumstances occur; specifically, it is potentially conscious in the sense that it can become part of a whole to which we attribute consciousness (say a human person). This topic raises some complex dilemmas concerning location and part/whole relations. Not every property of a whole is a property of its parts (redness), nor is every property of a part also a property of the whole (weighing less than one kilo). But some properties of parts are also properties of the whole (having some weight), some properties of a whole may also be properties of its parts (if the whole orchestra is in tune, then each instrument is in tune). Regarding location, it’s easier to say “Beth is conscious, but consciousness is not the kind of property that has a location.” Surely consciousness does not have a location in the same way that her hat does; still, if Beth is in California, we wouldn’t say that her consciousness resides in Tokyo. Is Beth’s consciousness located in each neuron of her brain, or in her brain as a whole, in her body as a whole, or in her personhood (whatever that is)? It seems most adequate to say that Beth’s consciousness is present in Beth as a whole. Clearly, these philosophy of mind questions are relevant to panentheism as well. Now consider an analogy. The cell as a whole is aware. And the actual chemical components of a given cell had the potential to become part of that cell. Take for example one of the cytosine molecules (chemical formula C4H5N3O) that pairs with guanine to make up a rung in the DNA double helix. This particular molecule is potentially aware in the sense that, if the right circumstances occur, it becomes part of a whole cell to which we attribute awareness. The analogy does two things. It treats both consciousness and awareness as whole-part relationships, which seems right. And it treats consciousness and awareness as existing in two forms: potential and actual. If the analogy holds, it allows us to say that consciousness already 7 exists in potentia, in the parts that compose a conscious person, and that, analogously, awareness exists in potentia in the parts that compose a cell. Now consider the NMfM Objection to emergent mentality, viz., that you can’t get consciousness from something that is not conscious. For a Cartesian, this is right; res cogitans and res extensa are dichotomous. For Descartes one can never emerge from the other because he presupposes from the start that no potential for this transition exists. By contrast, Western philosophy and science offer a number of ways of understanding the transition from potential to actual. We could explore science-based analogies such as superposition, as in the “collapse” of the (probabilistic) Schrödinger wave equation to a particular macrophysical state. 6 More broadly, you are already aware that Western metaphysics offers a rich legacy of ways to conceive the transition from potential to actual, for example in metaphysical systems inspired by Aristotle and in the dialectical philosophies of the German Idealists. These achievements offer rich resources for conceptualizing the transition from potentially aware to actually aware. To the extent that the transition becomes comprehensible, the NMfM Objection is answered. (3) Gradualist panentheistic panpsychism (1) God is a mental entity, the source of all mentality (2) Everything is in God (3) So all entities are mental entities. I argue in a recent article that the affirmation everything is in God is not sufficient to demarcate panentheism from various forms of classical theism.7 Still, a position would surely not count as panentheism if it does not affirm (2) in some sense. For its part, (1) is an affirmation about God that is held in one form or another across most of the history of theology. For example, even if God has a body, God is not simply a material being. Applied to God, “mental entity” could mean a variety of different things: has (or essentially has) mental attributes, or is solely mental in the sense of having no physical attributes, or is the source of all mentality, or is mentality as such, etc. If (3) then follows, then from panentheism one can infer panpsychism. Looking more closely at the alleged syllogism, one recognizes two things. First, its inference is not valid.8 Perhaps if (2) affirmed that “Everything is God,” the conclusion would follow. But that would be pantheism, not panentheism. The argument also begs for a closer analysis of what is meant by mental entity. Given the imprecision of the term, it can only serve as a rough label for a set of different concepts. Thus Uwe Meixner writes in the Brüntrup and Jaskola collection cited above, “The immediate consequence of this idea [panentheism] is that everything is in God (qua being in this total experience, which at the same time is the totality of all experiences), whether as an experience, 8 as a subject of experience, or as an object of experience.”9 Process theologians, influenced by Hartshorne, and then later by John Cobb, have explored these options in some detail. For example, Whitehead’s “objective immortality” affirms that only the outcome of creative activity (concrescence) is in God, whereas Marjorie Suchocki’s “subjective immortality” places the actual entity in its very becoming within God. The ambiguity of “mental entity” and of the “in” implied by panentheism makes it impossible to draw direct consequences from panentheism to panpsychism in the full or “maximal” sense.10 Maximal panpsychism is not entailed, for example, if the panentheistic “in” is interpreted as the spatial “in,” nor if it is the finite “in” the infinite. Unless and until it is shown that the “in” of panentheism requires every existing entity to be a mental entity (to have mentality as one of its own properties), one is not compelled to affirm maximal panpsychism. Of course, one can attempt to defend that view on other grounds. But panentheism alone will not get one there. Panentheism is helpful to the emergentist panpsychist, however. Even a minimal (panen)theism affirms divine creative intent and a continuing lure toward a telos that is consistent with the divine nature. Since the divide nature is or includes mentality, one has reason to expect that the telos is or includes mentality as well. That created mentality may not be instantiated at the time of the big bang; it may be the product of a universe continually lured toward the divine nature. This result is consistent with work on the stages of cosmic evolution in the science-and-theology discussion: the mathematical laws of astrophysics that reflect the constancy of God; the selforganizing patterns of biochemistry; the emergence of awareness and goal-oriented behavior at the dawn of the biosphere; and the gradual development of the capacity to know and worship God. Gradualist panentheistic panpsychism becomes the affirmation that God lures creation from “potentially aware” to “actually aware” in ways that preserve both the transcendence and the immanence of God. (4) “God in all things” and the ground of mentality We have discussed all things in God; now we must turn to the second “in” of panentheism: God in all things. (1) God is in all things. (2) Wherever God present, mentality is present. (3) Mentality is present in all things. Proposition (1) restates a major biblical theme, such as Acts 17:29, where Paul speaks of God as the one “in whom we live and move and have our being.” The same assertion is present in most forms of Western theism. Benjamin Göcke and others have shown that (1) is not distinctive to panentheism.11 Yet “God in all things” does express one of the two “in’s” that even a minimal 9 form of panentheism must affirm. Likewise, (2) should be non-controversial for theists. (3) thus represents a second entailment from panentheism to at least a minimal form of panpsychism. Again, though, we must ask: panpsychism in what sense? Skrbina puts the point nicely: There is a lingering and problematic sense in which Christian theology does allow for a weak form of panpsychism. If God is omnipresent, then he is obviously “in” all things; this points toward panentheism. If a portion of God is in a thing, and this portion assumes any sense of independent individuality, then this could qualify as a “monistic panpsychism.”12 Skrbina recognizes that “panentheism can be confused with panpsychism.” As we saw in the previous section, the two cannot be identified, but the former does imply, at minimum, an evolutionary sense of the latter. But could it be that panentheism implies panpsychism in a stronger sense than I have granted here? For example, Skrbina notes, “On the traditional view, God is omnipresent. If God represents spirit or mind, then all things can be said to contain mind—the mind of God.”13 The traditional doctrine of omnipresence by itself does not entail panpsychism, since God could be merely present to. But if God as mental actually exists within all things, as panentheists affirm, then wouldn’t a form of panpsychism stronger than emergentist panpsychism follow ― a panpsychism closer to the process version? In order to respond to this final objection to a gradualist panpsychism, it is helpful to take a closer look at the work of Thomas Nagel. Nagel is a non-theist who affirms a fundamental role for mind: “Mind, as a development of life, must be included as the most recent stage of this long cosmological history, and its appearance, I believe, casts its shadow back over the entire process and the constituents and principles on which the process depends.”14 Nagel holds that the gradual appearance of mind across cosmological history requires one to affirm that mind was present in the universe from the beginning as a fundamental principle, analogous to the way that physicists affirm that physical laws and mass/energy were present from the beginning. He argues: So if mind is a product of biological evolution—if organisms with mental life are not miraculous anomalies but an integral part of nature—then biology cannot be a purely physical science. The possibility opens up of a pervasive conception of the natural order very different from materialism—one that makes mind central, rather than a side effect of physical law.15 10 Examining this passage, however, one recognizes an important disanalogy between physics and biology. It’s true that physicists have to postulate that the fundamental physical particles and forces were present from the big bang, since they are essential for explaining even the first micro-seconds of cosmic history.16 But one does not have to postulate the presence of mental entities, or properties such as awareness, in the same way. One might want to affirm that mind is “central” in the first million years of cosmic history for other reasons, but there are no empirical reasons for doing so; it’s not a postulate that one actually needs at that point. Recall the “no mind from matter” (NMfM) Objection. Anti-emergentists such as Nagel and Cobb argue that, if we don’t postulate the presence of mind from the beginning, it can’t play a role later on, for example in biological or psychological explanations. That might have been true, emergentists respond, if the only options philosophy had were x exists or x does not exist. In fact, though, the resources available to us include powerful theories of the both/and, dialectical accounts of the changing proportions of mental and non-mental. The traditions stemming from Aristotle, for instance, offer compelling ways to think about transitions from potential to actual, and thus about the status of potentials, that is, things that exist in potentia. To name just one recent example, the scientist Stuart Kauffman ascribes to “the adjacent possible” a quasi-causal role in quantum physics and a role as a formal or structural cause in biological evolution.17 These conceptual resources, I suggest, deflate the power of the either/or assumption on which the NMfM Objection rests. Once we are able to set the NMfM Objection aside, an important area of shared agreement becomes visible, namely: I believe we may be able to agree that some ground for the gradual evolution of mentality must exist. Here we can affirm Nagel’s contention: “We ourselves are large-scale, complex instances of something both objectively physical from outside and subjectively mental from the inside. Perhaps the basis for this identity pervades the world.”18 Interestingly, when Nagel begins to speak of this “basis,” he cannot avoid theological language: Or maybe, as Colin McGinn (1989) famously argued, human beings are constitutively incapable of grasping the nature of the properties underlying consciousness; it could nonetheless be that the emergence of consciousness from non-consciousness is intelligible to God if not to us.19 More precisely, Nagel might have written, “the emergence of consciousness from nonconsciousness is intelligible to God … and intelligible to us if we include, however hypothetically, the notion of God and divine creation.” Many panentheists hold that divine mind precedes the creation of the universe, so that creation manifests divine intention and other features of God’s nature. The telos of God’s ongoing creative act, in the words of the Westminster Shorter Catechism formulates it: “Man's chief end is to glorify God, and to enjoy him forever.” This goal does not require that mentality have been actually present in created 11 beings from the first moment of cosmic history. But it does require that it have been present in potentia. That condition is met because the universe as a whole reflects the mind of its creator and the divine intent that mentality would eventually emerge and be manifested in the created world. Conclusion Thinking back over the argument, one begins to recognize that this particular debate represents one particular instance of a much broader project: reflecting one’s way toward sophisticated responses that address core theological commitments on the one hand and the best of contemporary philosophy and science on the other. Success is impossible without participants who are willing to keep the doors open in both directions. The Richard Dawkinses and Dan Dennetts on the one side construe the natural world in such a way that mentality, and thus God, cannot play a fundamental role. Strong advocates of the separateness of God, Cartesian dualism, or interventionist divine action close down the discussion from the other side. Process panpsychists and emergentist panpsychists do not need to make either of these two mistakes. We are familiar with theologians willing to do the hard work in philosophy and science to open up the discussion, but equally important are scientists such as Stuart Kauffman and secular philosophers such as Thomas Nagel. In the following passage, note how deeply the non-theist Nagel enters into the conceptual world of theism: My preference for an immanent, natural explanation is congruent with my atheism. But even a theist who believes God is ultimately responsible for the appearance of conscious life could maintain that this happens as part of a natural order that is created by God, but does not require further divine intervention. A theist not committed to dualism in the philosophy of mind could suppose the natural possibility of conscious organisms composed, perhaps supplemented by laws of psychophysical emergence. To make the possibility of conscious life a consequence of the natural order created by God while ascribing its actuality to subsequent divine intervention would then seem an arbitrary complication. Some form of teleological naturalism should for these reasons seem no less credible than an interventionist explanation, even to those who believe that God is ultimately responsible for everything.20 Nagel’s words here beautifully reflect the goal of this paper, and in some ways also its outcome. I have embraced teleological naturalism by eschewing mind/body dualisms and affirming mentality only where it is observable and plays some explanatory role. At the same time, I have pursued the questions from my standpoint as a panentheist. These two commitments required me to find a version of emergent mentality compatible with the double “in” of panentheism: all things in God and God in all things. The requirements of theology, philosophy, and science are 12 best met, I argued, by a gradualist panpsychism that affirms the actuality of divine mind, the potentiality of mentality from the moment of creation, and the actual emergence of mentality over the course of evolution.21 Endnotes 1 David Skrbina, Panpsychism in the West (Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2005), 21. 2 A.N. Whitehead, Process and Reality, corrected ed. (New York: Free Press, 1978). 3 Thomas Nagel, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 62. 4 Nagel, 20, 57. 5 Godehard Brüntrup and Ludwig Jaskolla, eds., Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2017), 6 Quantum physics offers an empirical basis for thinking about the concepts of the actual and the possible or potential. “Potentially aware” and “actually aware” can exist in a way that is analogous to a quantum superposition. (This is an argument that I developed in conversation with Brüntrup in conversation in October.) We know that the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum physics allows for states that are superpositions of actual and possible. In the famous thought experiment known as Schrödinger’s cat, the cat exists in a state of superposition of dead::alive until a measurement causes the collapse of the wave function into either dead cat or alive cat. A so-called quantum computer (if one can be constructed) would be powerful because each bit (“qubit”) could manifest not two but three different states: on, off, or indeterminate. So far physicists have been able to prepare up to 50 individual atoms in individual “traps.” These matrices extend quantum potentials far beyond the scale at which they normally occur. 7 Philip Clayton, “Prospects for Panentheism as Research Program,” European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11, No 1 (2019): 1-18. 8 To succeed, (2) would need to read “Everything is God.” (And even then there are problems, as we can learn from Shankara’s philosophy.) Panentheism is distinct from pantheism precisely because it does not make this assertion. 9 Uwe Meixner, “Idealism and Panpsychism,” in Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives, eds. Godehard Brüntrump and Ludwig Jaskola (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 399. 10 The question of whether panpsychism is helpful to the panentheist is an interesting one, although I will not have the chance to develop this argument fully here. Robert C. Whittmore maintains that panpsychism can become panentheism or, even more strongly, that panpsychism may imply or entail panentheism. He uses a passage from John Fisk: Panpsychism becomes panentheism in the realization that this “Life” manifest in all nature is “only a specialized form of the Universal Life,” which is that “eternal God indwelling in the universe, in whom we live and move and have our being.” For if, as noted earlier, God cannot be conceived as something outside the universe (as maintained in anthropomorphic theism), and if, as has been shown, we cannot identify Him or It with the universe phenomenally manifest (since this would be pantheism), then it must be that the one (theistic) alternative remaining is the truth: the universe is (as panentheism teaches) inside God! (John Fisk, quoted in Robert C. Whittemore, Makers of the American Mind: Three Centuries of American Thought and Thinkers [Apollo Editions, 1964], 303.) Whittemore is right to note the inference from panpsychism to panentheism, adding only that the inference does not require maximal panpsychism; it works just as well from the standpoint of maximal panpsychism. 11 See Clayton, “Prospects for Panentheism as Research Program.” 12 Skrbina, 274 n. 24. 13 David Skrbina, Panpsychism in the West (Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2005), 21. 14 Nagel, 8. This is part of his non-emergence thesis, that is, his claim that there are no truly emergent properties of complex systems. 15 Nagel, 15. 16 See Stephen Weinberg, The First Three Minutes (New York: Basic Books, 1977). 13 17 See Stuart A. Kauffman, Humanity in a Creative Universe (New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 2016). 18 Nagel, 42. 19 Philip Goff, “Panpsychism,” Stanford Journal of Philosophy (July 2017), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism/#AntiEmerArgu. 20 Nagel, 95. 21 As in my October paper for the Stuttgart conference, I am again grateful to Andrew M. Davis, who has worked as my research assistant on this paper. Our conversations together were important in formulating the key questions of this paper, and some of its key ideas emerged in discussions with him. (This is not to say that Mr. Davis agrees with the final thesis of the paper, however.) Every author knows the importance of the formative discussions that come just before writing, and it is a particular pleasure when these discussions can occur with one’s graduate student.